Mill's Proof of the Greatest Happiness Principle.
(1) if you see something, this proves that it is visible.
(2) Similarly, desiring something proves that it is desirable.
(3) The only thing that each person truly desires is happiness.
(4) The only thing that is truly desirable for a person is his or her own happiness.
(5) Hence each person should perform the actions that promote the greatest happiness.
Three Problems with this Argument:
First, (2) does not follow from (1). Visibility and desirability are not the same kinds of things.
Second,
(4) does not follow from (3). To assume that we can derive an "ought"
from an "is" is to make the naturalistic fallacy, which is a point made
by David Hume.
Third, (5) does not follow from (4). Just
because your own happiness is desirable does not mean that the happiness
of other people is also desirable.
Further Objections to Utilitarianism:
(1)
We cannot always predict what the consequences of our actions will be.
It is difficult if not impossible to judge the morality of an action
based on what the predicted consequences will be.
(2) It is
difficult to quantify pleasures. In other words, it is hard to
represent pleasures with numbers in order to determine if happiness will
be maximized by an action. Cost-benefit analysis is difficult if not
impossible.
(3) Also, the process of trying to determine if an
action will maximize happiness is time-consuming and difficult. It is
not practical that we will be able to do such a calculation before we
perform an action.
(4) Utilitarianism cannot explain special duties or obligations that we have to people like our friends, family and neighbors.
(5)
If we only care about sum total happiness, then there will be actions
that are good while these actions do cause a great amount of pain for
some people. For example, say that six of the seven dwarves decide to
torture, beat and murder the Dopey for fun. Even though Dopey
experiences a lot of pain, utility is still maximized because the other
dwarves are so happy. Thus a utilitarian must say that it is good for
the dwarves to murder Dopey.
(6) Utilitarianism fails to respect
individual rights. The rights of a single person can be violated as
long as the greatest good is still maximized.
(7) Utilitarianism
does not address the question of what kind of a person we should be.
The focus is entirely on consequences rather than the character of
people. For example, if I am offered a job as an assassin, I might
think that killing people for a job would be OK because even if I do not
take the job, someone else will. This means that whether or not I am
an assassin, the consequences are the same, hence the moral value of
either choice is equal.
(8) Pain is either entirely subjective (meaning that it does not exist) or perhaps pain is a good thing itself.
The
first three objections do not attack the theory but rather the practice
of the theory. Objections (1), (2) and (3) are all objections that the
theory is impractical and difficult (if not impossible) to use as a way
of making moral decisions. Objections (4), (5), (6), (7) and (8)
object on the grounds that the results of utilitarian theory will
conflict with strong moral intuitions or other reasons to consider when
deciding if an action is good or bad.